Wednesday, June 13, 2012

Hermeneutics & Documentary 
-OR- 
My Death to Modernism and Rebirth into Post-Modernism




There is something formless yet complete
That existed before heaven and earth.
How still how empty!
Dependent on nothing, unchanging,
All pervading, unfailing.
One may think of it as the mother of all things under heaven.
I do not know its name,
But I call it Meaning.”
(Lao tzu, 1891)



~



This morning, while taking a shower, I was visited by the ghost of Martin Heidegger. Dont forget the context” he told me. This bit of cryptic wisdom helped me with an issue I’d been having for several weeks. As my age and credit hours suggest a move on to the realer world is eminent, I had been experiencing an inexplicable discomfort with the direction I was headed intellectually. After 25 years of acting the good Mormon boy, about a year ago I finally experienced that rebirth I had always heard about. I realized I am spiritually terminal, and admitted that when it comes to the most important aspects of my sojourn on earth I am completely powerless. The desire to become, as Fleet Foxes put it, a functioning cog in some great machinery, serving something beyond me, welled up within me.
With the daunting prospect that where I fall among the disparate voices of academia may determine my usefulness in Gods kingdom, I searched for the opportunity to nail some things down. It slowly dawned on me that my former plan of immersing myself in research, hoping to come out the other end years later with some profound insights to leave as my legacy, did not take into account the Bibles warning against leaning on my own understanding and its vision of one-day-at-a-time discipleship. Being lost in theory-land while the world of practical concerns goes on without me is reasonable for a day or a week, but maintaining this detachment for the rest of my life now seemed unbearable. Ready to abandon my rational mind for more humble pursuits, my ears perked as a professor presented hermeneutics as an intriguing alternative to mainstream psychology. Compelled by a need to understand this new word, I committed myself to writing a paper entitled The Hermeneutics of Documentary, whatever that means. After consulting several helpful sources, I had made many connections, but little progress on the actual writing of the paper. Now three days past due, it sat on my laptop in the form of three detailed outlines, each taking an entirely different approach, and none leading to a discernible conclusion.
Looking back, this is understandable considering the nature of hermeneutics, which is often thought of as circular. Martin Packers Entering the Circle notes “axiomatic reconstructions and empiricist brute-data building blocks are both Rube Goldberg devices designed to enable people to escape from what they fear is a vicious circle: the circle of interpretation, the hermeneutic circle (Packer, 1989). Packer goes on to explain that, whereas modernist epistemologies have building blocks upon which understanding is constructed, for the post-modernist hermeneuticist, such foundations need not exist. Inescapably surrounded by meanings and interpretations, we need only a jumping in point. As long as it sheds light on the whole circle eventually, one jumping in point is as good as another.
So I took Heidegger’s call as an injunction to risk being annoyingly meta” and jump in with my own experiences leading up to, and including, the writing of this very paper. I hope to demonstrate how my quest for truth and usefulness (which are inexorably connected for neuts”) has often paralleled the historical discussions that lead to the hermeneutic tradition. We will see how, from this perspective, storytelling becomes the most valid means of understanding and explaining the universe. And we will look at the implications of this philosophy on the rich storytelling tradition of documentary.
Before we begin, a word on this papers arrangement: The ideas discussed in the next seven pages will at first appear to be unrelated to documentary. As you push on (maybe take a snack break), you will see how these nitty-gritties are essential tools for understanding the discussion of documentary that follows.



~



Last night, to pump ourselves up for our weekly dumpster dive, my friends and I watched a lovely documentary about thefreegan lifestyle called The Gleaners and I (Varda, 2000). In the film, director Agnes Varda provides a compelling account of those who find meaning and sustenance in the trash of others, considering the implications of such reverence for garbage on her own ephemeral nature. Afterward, having caught the introspective bug, I somehow got into a discussion with my friend Victoria about how one can contribute to academia without getting caught in what Martin Buber would call, the I-It mode (Buber, 1937). When in I-It mode, true brotherhood with those around you is eschewed for the pursuit of self—the academic manifestation of self being the drive to be right and have all the answers. As we then did the dumpster rounds, diving” with youthful abandon, I left the paper, the film, and the discussion behind and instinctively focused on the task at hand. Perfectly plump black-berries?! Unopened rice pudding?! Are those security cameras? Can yogurt go bad? We had to be picky with the produce, because there was more than we could ever use.
In his influential work Being and Time, Heidegger describes two attitudes toward the world we demonstrated that night. Present-at-hand” mode is the attitude of the scientist or theorist (Heidegger, Being and Time, 1953). As Victoria and I tried to conceptualize my role within academiaas if it had some kind of intrinsic, objective nature that could be combined with other concepts to elicit a logical truth somewhat like the reaction produced by combining two chemicals—we were in the present-at-hand. In such a pursuit, the realm of thought floating between us represented a laboratory, free from immediate concerns and the compromising variables which abound in the outside (orlived) world. Heidegger points out, and we will review this further later on, that objects and thoughts cannot be understood in such a contextless environment.
The alternative, which we dove into that night, is the attitude of ready-to-hand. Without theorizing or conceptualizing, we engaged with the things around us with the intention of achieving something. Heidegger says this is the more primordial attitude in that it is closer to our everyday experience (Heidegger, Being and Time, 1953). It is also the more accurate way of perceiving things because it automatically incorporates their context, which is inseparable from their reality. As we shimmied dumpster lids, opened trash bags, and exhumed cartons, theorizing was not necessary. In fact, if we were to stop and consider these objects as present-at-hand, our ability to dumpster dive would have been seriously impeded. We saw each bin not as a collection of molecules, but as portals to an exciting world of free food; our actions not as essentially conceptual, but as means to a fruitful end.

Greek Yogurt – Empiricism, Rationalism, and the Scientific Method

To understand this nights significance, let’s rewind about twenty years. From the time I first became aware of a world around me I recall searching for the best way to process it all. I wondered if my senses gave me access to some truth, all truth, or any truth, and what it might mean for something to be true that could never be perceived. Intrigued by the intuitive logic of the sentence 2 + 2 = 4, I pondered whether such rationality could ever be contradicted. I recall marveling at my own ability to doubt almost anything, including my own existence. Of course, this is my grown-up rendering of thoughts that originated in a childs vocabulary, but I believe most children consider such ideas in one way or another. As kids lack the means to express or defend themselves, such seemingly nonsensical thoughts are easily thrown out by well- intentioned parents and teachers. Most adults are understandably compelled to direct such youthful confusion toward the perspective that makes sense to them, and so a regular dose of Greek yogurt” is provided.
The tart substance to which I refer began with the bacteria of Platonic ideals and fermented in the culture of objective/subjective dualism. The idea is that the world is “out there,” unchanging and separate from us. We look out at this objective world through distorting lenses. This dualism is so pervasive that pointing it out often elicits an Of course, what else could it be? reaction. We instinctively see that the expression “time flies when youre having fun,” is not meant literally; that time, in reality,” remains constant, but our perception of time, when having fun, is distorted. But alternative conceptions of time and reality have existed in the West since the ancient Hebrews (Boman, 1960), not to mention the multiple and rich notions of the East, presumably appearing just as sensible and intuitive to them as our Greek conception appears to us.
Empiricism claims that the only things we can know for sure are those we can see. Rationalism, recognizing that our senses can be tricked, claims that the only things we can know for sure are those grounded in logic. Thus, by observing the interaction of these building blocks in increasingly complex structures, laws are identified, the goal being to predict what will happen given certain circumstances. By controlling the conditions with a knowledge of the rules, we can ensure certain outcomes.
I remember well being taught the process: a hypothesis is devised, the prescribed conditions are established, the outcome is compared to the original theory and it is declared either corroborated or falsified. The scientific method combines rationalism and empiricism, translating observables into data from which conclusions can be drawn using logic. The goal is to avoid any kind of bias. Once this has been accomplished, the reasoning goes, there will be nothing left but pure,” uninterpreted reality.
I spent most of my undergraduate degree viewing interpretation as a second-class citizen to the objective truths identified by the scientific method. As a student of film, I of course gloried in the profundity of stories, but believed them beautiful manifestations of the underlying principles that were of fundamental importance; distractions made by those who could not get the hang of the detached, unfeeling laws just waiting to be discovered. Convinced of cinema’s hold on the human mind, I looked at it as a stimulus that elicits certain cognitive and behavioral responses. If I could only break it down somehowgrab hold of its untarnished essence—then I could generate some universal algorithm for engaging with media that, just maybe, could increase empathy, augment charity, or decrees aggression; variables I saw as equally quantifiable and contextless as the stimuli that produced them.
Switching back and forth between the sciences and humanities necessitated some impressive mental gymnastics. Seeing that spectator engagement and phenomenology were crucial variables to understanding the effects of cinema, the rationalism of semiotics was the only option for a hopeless Greek such as myself (see my Connoting Emotional Dependence in The King of Comedy”).
This semester I am taking three classes that continue to blow my mind by presenting (finally!) an alternative that addresses and expands the forgotten questions I had as a child. This paradigm shift began with a few simple observations.

Problems with the Scientific Worldview, and the Hermeneutic Solution

Proponents of the scientific method claim that it is value-neutral; that its application will automatically reveal truth. But Martin Heidegger points out that any method devised to uncover truth prefigures the nature of the object of investigation (Heidegger, Being and Time, 1953). For example, if one were to enter a cave, determined to gain an understanding of what lies therein, and brought only a tape recorder, they would reveal a preconceived notion that the nature of the cave is essentially auditory, that perhaps all its other relevant attributes may be derived from the audio that will be captured. Such a method would, because of its faulty starting assumption, miss many of the cave’s most important attributes, and true understanding could not be achieved.
And so, to determine what method is most appropriate for investigating an object (or whether a method will be useful at all), one must first make some assumptions. The scientific method cannot discover through an experiment whether or not experimentation can get to the essence of things, it can only reveal truths consistent with itself.
The basic, unproven assumption on which this method rests is that the universe is deterministic; a view that for everything that happens there are conditions such that, given them, nothing else could happen (Long, 1974).  This view is in direct opposition to my own beliefs about, and experience with, moral agency, which requires possibilities. I had an awareness of this inconsistency before, but with seemingly no alternative, I placed this concern on myfigure out later” shelf. But as philosophy professor Richard Williams points out, agency is a watershed issue which must be first affirmed or rejected before moving down any philosophical stream (Williams, 2005). The final blow that freed me from my modernist shackles was the simple, self- evident observation that No one has ever experienced uninterpreted reality, and no one ever will.” This being the case, what could possibly be achieved by discussing a realm of ideal forms that could never be in any way accessed? The dominoes were falling.
Michael Inwood summarizes the implications of this idea better than I could in his book Heidegger: A Very Short Introduction (note: in the following quote, Dasein” refers to the Human Being):
The distinction between what is so in itself and what is so only for us is a distinction drawn from our own understanding of being, not from the Dasein-independent nature of things. If there were no Dasein, there would be no such distinction: every being would be on a par with every other being, with no foreground and no background, no depth and no superficiality. We do not have the resources to describe such a condition: every description we propose is already encumbered with our own understanding of being, our own significant world. Why should we say that, in our familiar Dasein-ridden world, a hammer is in itself a collection of molecules and only for us a tool? There is no reason to do so. It follows from no plausible account of a Dasein-free, hammerless world. It gives an unwarranted priority to the theoretical investigations of the scientist over the circumspect concern of the craftsman. For such reasons as these Heidegger believes that ontology and phenomenology coincide. (p. 63)
That’s good stuff.
An astute observer will note some possible problems with this perspective. If, as it seems to suggest, science cannot give us access to the objective, why does it work so well? Surely it must be a better way of looking at the world—look at what it has produced! The implication here is that if something doesnt “work,” or meet our needs the way we want it to, it is not based on truth. But to work” is a meaning in itself, indetachable from our everyday, interpreted concerns. As Inwood put it Newtons and Euclids systems both worked because they were ingenious systems for representing natural phenomena in a manner relevant to our need to control and manipulate nature, not because they mirrored an objective reality (p. 22). Consider the failure of this unbiased method, which works so well on physical objects, to produce similar advances in psychology, which seeks control over human behavior. With all its confident language and lofty theories, no one seriously claims the project of mental and emotional health has progressed in the last century anything close to the mastery we’ve achieved over the physical realm. The hermeneutic perspective suggests an intriguing answer to this troubling inconsistency.
The basic premise of the hermeneutic perspective is that there is no distinction between the subjective and the objective. As these two concepts are often perceived as opposites, some explanation is in order. First, lets consider the idea of interpretation; often considered a purely subjective endeavor. To interpret is to assign meaning to something. By the very nature of meaning, this entails one significance being claimed from an array of possible significances. When someone explains what they meant by something, they are pointing out that their expression could be taken different ways, and the intention was to express this one rather than that one. Something that had no potential to exist otherwise would not mean anything, it would just be. If a robot says I love you whenever a button is pressed, that expression has no meaning because the robot could not have done otherwise. As every event and object may be interpreted a number of ways depending on the perspective of the one doing the interpretation, it appears, to the dualist, that interpretation must be fundamentally different from reality. From this perspective, everything has a real” nature; an objective way of being that cannot be interpreted otherwise.
The hermeneutic perspective challenges the premises on which this dualism rests. If we reconsider the above assertion that “something that could not exist otherwise would not mean anything, it would just be,” a subtle assumption reveals itself. This idea assumes that to exist is to be stagnant, or to have a fixed nature. Current advances in quantum physics are calling into question this idea, as we discover elemental building blocks that exhibit the qualities of two diametrically opposed modes of existence simultaneously (Malin, 2001). The hermeneutic argument, put forth before the rise of quantum physics, takes this idea of a dual nature even farther, claiming that everything exists as meaning. That is, when we assign a meaning to something, we are in a way enabling it to exist, or at least participating in its existence. This does not necessarily imply a solipsism wherein objects and events do not exist if they are not perceived, but simply that they exist as an array of possible meanings, not as a stagnant entity independent of all context.
Not even time is considered as the objective flowing stream we often imagine it to be. The past is not a series of unchangeable events, but an interpretation that gets its meaning from its relationship to the experienced present and the prospective future. A veteran with a missing hand could interpret his injury as a noble sacrifice for the next generation when he becomes a father, or a sign that God does not exist upon learning that it precludes him from some employment opportunity. But he could never not interpret it.
Because everything in the experienced world has an assigned, contextual meaning inherent to its very existence, any approach to inquiry based on an objective/subjective dualism is inherently less truthful than explicitly interpretive accounts. There is no escaping interpretation; we cannot create detached spheres from whence we can peer out on an objective world. A perspective that advocates being value neutral” reveals its bias by ironically not valuing that which embraces interpretation. The prominent hermeneutic psychologist Carl Jung pointed out The experiment imposes limiting conditions on nature, for its aim is to force her to give answers to questions devised by man. Every answer of nature is therefore more or less influenced by the kind of questions asked, and the result is always a hybrid product. The so- called ‘scientific view of the world’ based on this can hardly be anything more than a psychologically biased partial view (Jung, 1960, p. 6).
Now back to the puzzling absence of advancement in mainstream psychology, a discipline sopping with Greek yogurt. If reality exists fundamentally as experienced meanings, doesn’t it make sense that interpreting that-which-does-not-interpret (rocks, molecules, etc.) would elicit results much more readily than interpreting interpreters (human beings). Accounting for the natural world is a much simpler projectmolecules do not care what story you tell to describe them, or whether that story coincides with the one they tell of themselves. But to explain my neighbor, who is constantly in the process of explaining himself, is a fundamentally different operation. In fact, Packer suggests the few behavioral models that do seem to get some traction with people, such as economics, may work only because our understanding of the causal regularities of nature constrains social life (Packer, 1989, p. 26). This suggests that the sciences and the humanities are actually in the same business, just with different subject matter; one tells stories about nature, the other about humans.

The Camera and the Single Shot

A common question for someone trying to grapple with this new way of looking at the world has direct relevance to documentary. They ask What if you captured a moment on video? Couldn’t such a document potentially reveal that one persons interpretation of an event was ‘wrong?’” Bill Nichols discusses the exalted status we often give the camera in his book Introduction to Documentary: “The ability of the photographic image to reproduce the likeness of what is set before it, its indexical quality, compels us to believe that it is reality itself re- presented before us, while the story or proposal presents a distinct way of regarding this reality.” Perhaps the camera’s technological paternity, with its sleek, unrufflable frame, unconsciously reminds us of objectivity. (Note: for the sake of compactness, from now on only visual qualities will be discussed, although each concept applies equally to the audible)
Let’s first compare this indexical quality to that of our own imaging apparatus. We go through life looking through our own eyes, and so must accept that our perspective will always be different from that of others. But a film document lets everyone look through the same eyes. If two witnesses of a crime later disagree over the color of the perpetrator’s hat, it is easy to see that one of them has an incorrect interpretation. Show them a security tape that shows the hat to be red and the discussion is overaffirming that one persons interpretation can be wrong.”
Although such an experience would necessitate the incorrect witness to revise his memory, taking into account the evidence at hand, this in no way disqualifies the hat’s redness from the realm of interpretation. What we have here is simply a progression of interpretation. Consider the following pair of assertions:

1. One witness reports the hat was red while the other witness reports the hat was green.”

2. Both witnesses now agree the hat was red.”

Both statements are equally accurate, and both would be relevant in an investigation. Such an observation cannot be removed from the implications it may have for, say, a suspect who was found wearing a red hat. Inwood sheds more light on this issue in his intro to Heidegger:
An assertion is true, it is suggested, if and only if it corresponds to a fact. This gives Heidegger two reasons for disputing the theory. For if the theory is correct, there must first be an assertion to correspond to a fact and secondly a fact for it to correspond to. But neither of these items can fit the role assigned to it by the theory… There is no pre- packaged portion of meaning sufficiently independent of the world and of entities within it to correspond, or fail to correspond, to the world. Words and their meanings are already world-laden. (48-50)
The comparison of the shot to a statement makes this concept’s application to film clear. Besides, as Packer points out, what counts as an observation depends on current theory” (Packer, 1989, p. 21). If the current theory of what happened does not require knowledge of the perpetrators headwear, the color of the hat would not even be considered evidence and, unless assigned some other significance by one of the witnesses (such as its fashion value), would likely be forgotten.
Because time is unidirectional change, neither the human eye nor the camera lens can take in light directly from the past or future. Film’s ability to reproduce light, captured in the past, in the present—its temporality—does not, as Andre Bazin suggested, mummify the image in the sense of taking it out of the flow of time (Bazin, 1960). It instead converts what was captured into a form that can be encountered and interpreted afresh in the spectators own present. It then instantly takes its rank in the interpreted past, as new experiences add to, color, or detract from the meaning of what was experienced. Leni Riefenstahls sympathetic portrayal of the 1934 Nazi Party Congress, Triumph of the Will, provides a convenient example of a film that has been reinterpreted several times over the years in light of shifting meanings surrounding World War II. To declare one interpretation right” and another wrong is to suggest the existence of some neutral way of seeing the film that can serve as a criterion. One perspective can take into account (interpret) more information about the making of the film, but while this may render their reading more useful, it hardly makes it more objectively true.
Yet many documentarians continue to imbue the camera with the magical ability to capture reality untainted by human bias. Influential filmmaker Albert Maysles has been known to side with the notorious empiricist Sir Francis Bacon by adopting as his personal motto the quote "The contemplation of things as they are, without error or confusion, without substitution or imposture, is in itself a nobler thing than the whole harvest of invention" (Tammer, p. 1). His claim, that a cameraman can Get it down as no different, no better, no worse than what it is” (Levin, 1971, p. 251), is challenged by Frederick Wiseman, whose straight-forward films are often classified alongside the Maysles’ observational docs. In a famous interview he asserted Of course there's conscious manipulation! Everything about a movie is manipulation (Wiseman, 2012).
It has been pointed out by countless filmmakers and scholars that placing the camera within a space is inherently taking a position on the nature of what is to be captured. Simply standing aside and letting the action unfold,” as an impartial” scientist might, is making the value-laden assumption that the event being captured is best understood as not involving the camera.
So, we see, the idea that the camera is somehow exempt from the all-encompassing meaning soup” of realitythe idea that tripods stand on neutral groundis fundamentally ill- conceived, for camerasare not detached: they are blind. They don’t see from nowhere, they see nothing (Packer, 1989, p. 28). Only we humans are capable of truly seeing, and what we see is significance.

Montage as Complex

The prospect of representing an objective reality becomes even more complex when we consider the edited documentary; essentially one extended collage of ideas and images. The creation of meaning, via juxtaposition, here is obvious. The most straight-forward example is narration, wherein the viewer is told the meaning of the image presented. With the technique of montage, first described by Eisenstein, an emotionally charged image is placed after a more ambiguous (ripe with potential meaning) image, and the recent past instantly acquires a new meaning in light of the present.
As experienced rationalists, it is tempting for us to see montage as a process of constructing a logical argument. When a solid logical case is made, it appears there can be little wiggle room for differing perspectives. Perhaps this—intuitive, rational thoughtcan be the arbiter of interpretations, coming down solidly on one side or another.
But there’s a problemalthough the well-known syllogism All men are mortal, and Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal,” is, by the rules of language, true given its premises, we see that the premises exist not in the world of logic, but in the lived world of human experience. This does not escape interpretation, because interpretation is more fundamental. If there is no such thing as an objective, contextless antecedent or consequent, syllogistic reasoning becomes nothing more than a stimulating, though often quite useful, mental exercise.
In his book Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle, Carl Jung present an alternative to rationalist conceptions of reality, emphasizing that We must remember that the rationalistic attitude of the West is not the only possible one and is not all-embracing, but is in many ways a prejudice and a bias that ought perhaps to be corrected (Jung, 1960, p. 69). In search of such an alternative epistemology, which he believed would account for many important aspects of life left untouched by rationalism, he dedicated many years to studying the mythologies of various cultures, presenting for occidental consideration ideas such as the poem which heads this paper. The idea of synchronicity maintains that, just as events may be grouped by cause, they may also be grouped by meaning (Hott, 2011, p. 1). Such a grouping of meaning forms what Jung referred to as a “complex which is “the sum of ideas referring to a particular feeling-toned event” (Cope, 2006, p. 105).
In film, montage may be seen similarly as the linking of ideas and images by meaning in an expanding network of significance.
We have already alluded to the court-room analogy, with its evidence-based explanation of events. Documentarians such as Andrew and Annelie Thorndike and Errol Morris have embraced this prosecutorial role, piecing together evidence to account for what happened and what should be done about it (a movement thoroughly documented in Erik Barnouws Documentary: A History of the Non-Fiction Film [1974, pp. 172-182]). The legal system has long been aware that it was not in the business of making judgments based on someobjective truth” about what really happened.” Kim Lane Scheppele in her work Telling Stories, published in the Michigan Law Review, states in no uncertain terms that The resolution of any individual case in the law relies heavily on a courts adoption of a particular story, one that makes sense, is true to what the listeners know about the world, and hangs together (Scheppele, 1989, p. 2076). W. Lance Bennett and Martha S. Feldman further claim that The use of stories to reconstruct the evidence in cases casts doubt on the common belief that justice is a mechanical and objective process” in their book Reconstructing Reality in the Courtroom (Bennett, 1981, p. 1).
This account rings true to most of us; we inhabit a world of values and emotions that can seem equally non-rational and undeniable. This too makes more sense of the documentary, with its tradition of rhetoric and inevitable appeal to ethos and pathos. A film argument, as with our own internal rationalizing, can be compelling in its logic, but it is never exclusively logical, always depending on an underlying layer of malleable meaning. For someone whose emotional or spiritual compass points north, logic rarely persuades them to turn south, no matter how air- tight it may appear. Wiseman recognized this when saying of his own films If you like it, it's an interpretation. If you don't like it, it's a lie (Wiseman, 2012, p. 1).

A Moral Foundation

But the wishy-washiness implied by this last quote—the idea that no perspective can ever be definitively declared more true than anothersmacks of a dangerous relativism. But with the hermeneutic perspective this need not necessarily be the case. Of course there is such a thing as a straight-up lie, which occurs when someone purposely fails to take into account all the factors involved, or invents factors that do not exist in reality. That’s right, just because there is no objective, separate, atemporal reality, does not mean reality does not exist. Hermeneutics is not purely subjective; it is, if you will, sobjective—the objective and subjective are inseparable, considered to be the same thing.
An example my professor shared that helped me with this concept invites us to imagine that a little girl has been struck and killed by a car. I know, an unpleasant thought. This event can be interpreted many different ways depending on one’s relationship to the girl and one’s understanding of what led to the accident. These different interpretations are all equally representative of what happened, yet they are constrained by the event’s reality, which cannot be interpreted in just any way. It could not, for example, be understood as anything but a tragedy, though it be of the lugubrious variety or the silver-lined cloud variety.
Back to the above quote by Wiseman: He closes his remarks by admitting that Everything about these movies is a distortion” (Wiseman, 2012, p. 1). Presumably he meant to imply that the act of filmmaking is inherently distorting, as indeed anyone believing in the existence of an objective realm just out of the camera’s reach would be obliged to believe. But the hermeneuticist enjoys the hope of achieving an interpretation that is not distorted, because it is reality. Wisemans self-deprecating statement may reveal an underlying uneasiness he has about the observational mode he employs, with its preconceptions of the objective nature of the lens’ prisoner. It never fully yields to interrogation, and so what is presented in the final film inevitably feels incomplete.
So he is not wrong; his work may in fact be skewed, but not inevitably so. Inwood talks about how an interpretation can be distorted, but not in the common usage of corresponding less to reality:
There are falsehoods. But… it is more a matter of covering things up, of distorting them, and this may be done in other ways than by making false assertions, by omission or by non-verbal actions. Truthconsists of uncovering things. It consists of illuminating things or shedding light on them. It is a matter of degree, of more or less, rather than an either-or. (Inwood, 1997, pp. 50-51)
The possibility of one view being more or less distorted than another opens the door for an alternative means of assessing interpretation. If it can be said that misrepresenting something by not taking into account all its constitutive aspects is morally wrong, we see that any perspective can be assessed for its moral value. Though this is not an inevitable conclusion of the hermeneutic perspective, it is clear by the writings of theistic existentialists such as Soren Kiekegaard that this option is available for the faithful hermeneuticist. His statement that death is the light in which great passions, both good and bad, become transparent (Kierkegaard, 2000, p. 124) suggests that taking into account the inevitability of death can result in passions (energized perspectives) that are morally good. If morality is considered a meaning that emanates from God, then accessing His divine light becomes a means for identifying the best (most morally good) perspective. This may be what Heidegger was getting at when he said Every philosophy, as a human thing, intrinsically fails; and God needs no philosophy (Heidegger, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, 1978, p. 76).
But if one interpretation can be considered more morally good than another, doesn’t that bring up the problems of subjective/objective dualism by positing that an immoral perspective fails to match up to the best” perspective, considered to be static and timeless? Not necessarily. If we consider morality as a living entity, rather than a fixed index of superlative approaches to every conceivable situation, we see that morality, like our own lived experience, can be relative to context and still exist. If such an index existed there would be no need for an active God—He could simply drop off the guidebook and let us study our way to sanctity. Instead, He sent His son to enact that eternal Good which is not reducible to laws or ideals. Christ did not say He exemplified, understood, or lived in accordance with the truth—He boldly declared I am the truth” (John 14:6). If the Truth is a living being that emanates light in which moral meanings are assigned, the epistemology of revelation becomes key. While no known method can reveal objective truth in itself, Truth may actually present itself to the humble, faithful seeker.
I think this is the key. Considering that everything exists as meaning, and telling stories about the world in light of a divine context, the life of a theorist may be saved from perpetual present-at-hand detachment.

Divine Context and Usefulness

To truly comprehend one’s context is to assume a purpose in relation to it. Teleological explanations of human motivation hold that any action, including speech, is taken for the sake of some goal. The modernist assumption of linear time holds only the past responsible for pushing” us into action. But when the meaning of the future (which exists in the form of goals and expectations) is considered just as real as the meaning of the past, our actions can be seen as truly caused by the selfby our own agentic choice to value a goal and pursue it. So when we learn to turn our gaze to context in the pursuit of meaning, a certain course of action is indicated and instinctively ventured into. When a modernist philosopher, mapping objective reality with pen, paper, and his rational mind, does not notice the cry of his infant in the next room, it is because he is out of his immediate context. Direct his attention to the fact, and a caring father will risk losing his train of thought to attend to the matter at hand. This new purpose is sure to ensue automatically, without theorizing, just by virtue of recognizing the present, meaning-laden context.
Understanding that conceptualizations are, first and foremost, acts of expression (whether in the form of words or montage), theoretical inquiry can be redeemed from the irrelevance of abstraction. While considering the construct of love as somehow containing its own qualities outside the context of a relationship may impede one’s readiness-to-hand, the expression I love you,” when said by a nonrobot who could do otherwise, can be very helpful indeed.
This is the mode I recognized in Varda’s The Gleaner’s and I. By acknowledging her own role in processing these events, she assumed a humble position in relation to the viewer. Never implying her film was “merely a perspective,” as if other films could achieve more objectivity, she presents her subject matter with a “this is my experience for your consideration,” sense of proportion. This is inviting and therefore useful, as I am more inclined to absorb what she has to offer when it is accurately advertized.
This approach does not come naturally for those still stumbling in the shadows of subjective/objective dualism. I know the feeling all too well of discovering some earth-shattering truth, and then despairing when others fail to accept it. Perspective—so necessary for the here- and-now interaction of the ready-to-handcan be lost as allegiance to such a finding— demanded by its obvious truthy-nessresults in the collateral damage of closed minds, as listeners resist an expression which purposely leaves out morality, perspective, and context. If one caught in such a monologue can snap out of the present-at-hand, they may be able to see that what is really going onthe true nature of the exchange—is not the transmission of pure truth from one mind to another, but the self-centered display of a Greek mind trying to assert its rightness.
What does this imply about the various approaches of documentary, with its long tradition of grappling with just such issues? Some categorizations can help us identify an ideal of sorts. Placing specific films on a spectrum from expository to observational, it appears the more perspectival (often considered manipulative) mode of exposition escapes the scientific distortion of detachment. But a heavily narrated documentary might easily grab hold of some concept and not let go until the whole world conforms to it, as in many a network’s construals of current events. Such obstinacy obscures the purposes of connection, expansion, or persuasion, as the presenter feels constrained by some Platonic ideal. Cinema verite, the laudable attempt to tell stories that include the presence of the camera, appears the safest bet for one who admits that reality is inherently contextual. But the common denominator here is context, and it seems nearly every documentary mode is capable of taking this into account. Even the observational documentarian may, be laying bare her rationale for standing aside, present a compelling work that avoids the traps of objectivism.
Now that I think of it, many of the films that have most resonated with me have displayed this contextual-usefulness. Ross McElwee’s Bright Leaves (2003) rings true precisely because it lays context on the table for our inspection and then goes to it, as does the BYU production Home Movies (2011). Several of my favorite books take a similar tact, framing their principles by first recognizing the nature of the interaction. This approach, employed to inviting affect by the best missionaries, recognizes first that we are all in this together, and that no one but God has a monopoly on truth. Such an approach has the potential to do much good, for as we recognize that storytelling is the ultimate means of penetrating reality, context-conscious documentaries gain the ability to shed light on aspects of reality accessible to no other story-telling method, including the scientific one.



~



This is my best attempt at explaining the Aha! moment I experienced in the shower that morning. My efforts at writing a paper on hermeneutics using a nonhermeneutic method were failing. As soon as Martin’s ghost prompted me to include the context, I knew what I had to do. By conveying this papers personal significance in the paper itself, my intention is to enact the very approach being presented. Though I will undoubtedly have to return to the present-at-hand throughout my life, I am optimistic that this paper will mark the beginning of a new and useful career as one who humbly tells stories about stories in God’s kingdom.
             Thanks for indulging me.


Works Cited

Barnouw, E. (1974). Documentary: A History of the Non-Fiction Film. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.

Bazin, A. (1960). The Ontology of the Photographic Image. Film Quarterly, 4-9.

Bennett, W. L. (1981). Reconstructing Reality in the Courtroom: Justice and Judgment in the
American Courtroom. New York, NY: Rutgers University Press.

Boman, T. (1960). Hebrew Thought Compared With Greek. New York, NY: SCM
Press LTD.

Buber, M. (1937). I and thou. Berlin, Germany: Continuum.

Cope, T. (2006). Fear of Jung: The Complex Doctrine and Emotional Science. London: Karnac
Books Ltd.

Eds. Jackson, A. P. (2005). Turning Freud Upside Down: Gospel Perspectives on Psychotherapy's
Fundamental Problems. Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press.

Eisenstein, S. (1947). Film Sense. Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace & Company.

Heidegger, M. (1953). Being and Time. Albany, NY: State University of New York.

Heidegger, M. (1978). The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.

Hott, V. (2011, Novembe 14). Simply Laced. Retrieved April 6, 2012, from In Sync With

Inwood, M. (1997). Heidegger: A Very Short Introduction. New York, NY: Oxford University
Press.

Jung, C. (1960). Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.

Kierkegaard, S. (2000). Soren Kierkegaard. In C. A. Dingle, Memorable Quatotations:
Philosophers of Western Civilization (p. 124). Lincoln, NE: Writers Club Press.

Lao-tzu. (1891). Tao Te Ching. New York, NY: Vintage Books.

Levin, G. R. (1971). Documentary Explorations: 15 Interviews With Film-Makers. New York,
NY: Doubleday.

Long, A. (1974). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. Los Angeles, CA:
University of California Press.

Malin, S. (2001). Nature Loves to Hide: Quantum Physics and Reality, a Western Perspective.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Packer, M. J. (1989). Entering the Circle: Hermeneutic Investigation in Psychology. Albany, NY:
State University of New York Press.

Scheppele, K. L. (1989). Telling Stories. Michigan Law Review, 2073-2098.

Tammer, P. (n.d.). Interview with Albert Maysles. Retrieved April 6, 2012, from Inner Sense:

Varda, A. (Director). (2000). The Gleaners and I [Motion Picture].

Williams, R. (2005). Agency. In A. P. Jackson, Turning Freud Upside Down (pp. 116-142).
Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press.

Wiseman, F. (2012). Quotes On Documentary. Retrieved April 5, 2012, from Documentary is
            Never Neutral: http://documentaryisneverneutral.com/words/docquotes.html